On not Knowing a Language:

 Chomsky’s Review of Skinner Reconsidered

 

John Collins (UEA)

 

"It as little occurs to me to get involved in the philosophical

 quarrels and arguments of my times as to go down an ally

 and take part in a scuffle when I see the mob fighting there."

— Arthur Schopenhauer, 1828-30, 'Adversaria' in Manuscript Remains, Vol. 3: Berlin Manuscripts (1818-1830). Oxford: Berg Publishers, 1989, §126.

 

Proposal: Elimination of Epistemology of Language

 

The concept of knowledge and its cognates have no substantive (explanatory) role to play within theoretical linguistics.

 

The language faculty - the object of theoretical interest - is not a propositional structure. It is not a duplicate of our theory inside the head of the speaker/hearer.

 

Components of FL:

(a) Lexicon (features)

(b) Merge - internal/external (combinatorial procedure)

(c) Expressions (output profile - ‘instructions’ to the external systems)

 

“But do we not know the principles which explain our acceptability judgments/knowledge?”

 

(i)    Harry appealed to [the boys]i [PROi to like each otheri].

(ii) *Harryi appealed to [the boys]i [PROi to like himselfi].

(iii)  Harryi appeared to [the boys] [<Harry>i to like himselfi].

(iv)*Harryi appeared to [the boys] [<Harry>i to like each otheri].

 

Compare:

 

(v)  It appeared [to the boys] [that Harry likes himself/*each other].

(vi) It appealed [to the boys] [that Harry likes himself/*each other].

 

The acceptable interpretation of (v) is a close paraphrase of (iii), with the matrix verb having no external q-role to assign - Harry internally merges as the goal of EPP probe; its nominative Case is checked. An alternative derivation - (v) - checks EPP via expletive external merge  (NB: the context of Harry is transparent in both cases.) Appear assigns double internal q-roles in both cases: experiencer and (clausal - finite/infinite) patient.

 

The acceptable interpretation of (vi) differs from the failed interpretation of (ii). In the former, no agent q-role is assigned; appeal makes the same q-role assignment as appear. (NB: the prepositional argument of appear is optional at PF (within convergent PHON); if deleted, an implicit argument appears to be present as an expression of lexical content.) In (ii), on the other hand, Harry is the agent - no internal merge to check Case occurs (NB: PRO [-Case] occupies the agent position of like, and so serves as the (failed) antecedent of the reflexive) The reciprocal readings of (v) and (vi) are blocked in each case, for reciprocals in finite clauses require a clause-mate antecedent.

 

Moral: We explain the phenomena in terms of interpretable (e.g., q-role) and uninterpretable (e.g., Case, EPP) lexical features. We have no recourse to propositional principles.

 

 

Some Quotations from Chomsky

 

“… in English one uses the locutions "know a language," "knowledge of language," where other  (even similar) linguistic systems use such terms as "have a language," "speak a language," etc. That may  be one reason why it is commonly supposed (by English speakers) that some sort of cognitive relation holds  between Jones and his language, which is somehow "external" to Jones; or that Jones has a "theory of his language," a theory that he "knows" or "partially knows."… One should not expect such concepts to play a role in systematic inquiry into the nature, use, and acquisition of language, and related matters, any more than one expects such informal notions as "heat" or "element" or "life" to survive beyond rudimentary stages of the natural sciences.

¾ Noam Chomsky/B. Stemmer, 1999, ‘An On-Line Interview with Noam Chomsky: on

     the Nature of Pragmatics and Related Issues’, Brain and Language, 68, 393-401.

     p.397.

 

“There is no problem for ordinary language… But there is no reason to suppose that common usage of such terms as language or learning (or belief and numerous others like them), or others belonging to similar semantic fields in other linguistic systems, will find any place in attempts to understand the aspects of the world to which they pertain. Likewise, no one expects the commonsense terms energy or liquid or life to play a role in the sciences, beyond a rudimentary level. The issues are much the same.”

¾ Noam Chomsky, 2000, ‘Linguistics and Brain Science’, in A. Marantz, et al. (eds.),

     Image, Language, Brain, MIT, p.23

 

 

 

Origin of a Mistake: 1959 ’n All That

 

Chomsky’s famous 1959 review of Skinner’s Verbal Behavior is most often taken to be an argument for a representational theory of mind, under which intentional vocabulary is co-opted for scientific purposes. The reading goes as follows:

 

The Wrong reading

(i) The behaviourists (Skinner) argued that colloquial mentalistic vocabulary is non-explanatory of behaviour. It may be fruitfully replaced by learning theoretic vocabulary - stimulus, response, control, reinforcement, probability, etc. - which places the cause of behaviour  in environmental variables, not internal states.

 

(ii) The learning theoretic vocabulary is in fact non-explanatory; the mentalistic vocabulary does a better job.

 

(iii) Mentalism is ‘the only president we’ve got’.

 

(iv) Therefore, mentalism provides an appropriate basis for the explanation of behaviour.

 

 

The Right Reading

(i) The behaviourists (Skinner) argued that colloquial mentalistic vocabulary is non-explanatory of behaviour. It may be fruitfully replaced by learning theoretic vocabulary - stimulus, response, control, reinforcement, probability, etc. - which places the cause of behaviour  in environmental variables, not internal states.

 

(ii) But the terms of the new nomenclature are “mere homonyms, with at most a vague similarity of meaning” to the vocabulary defined in the lab. In fact, the terms are “metaphoric” of our “mentalistic” ones, which “simply disguises a complete retreat to mentalistic psychology” (pp.552-3).

 

(iii) Therefore, the “terminological revision adds no objectivity to the familiar mentalistic mode of description” (p.556), especially when “used with the full vagueness of the ordinary vocabulary” (p.559).

 

(iv) But is just doesn’t follow that the mentalistic vocabulary is explanatory. “It is futile to inquire into the causation of verbal behavior [or any other type of behaviour] until much more is known about the specific character of this behavior” (p.575).

 

(Quotations are taken from the reprint of Chomsky’s review in J. Fodor and J. Katz, 1964, (eds.), The Structure of Language (pp.547-578). Prentice-Hall.) 

 

 

A Typically Egregious Thought

“The refusal to get bogged down in merely verbal disputes is crystallized in the popular move, initiated by Chomsky, of abandoning the word ‘knowledge’ in favour of some surrogate… ‘tacit knowledge’, ‘competence’, ‘cognizing’, ‘representation’, or even simply ‘R’.

     This terminological manoeuvre has its place but hardly eliminates the importance of reflecting on the character of the corresponding relatum. After all,… we are presupposing attributions of cognizing to be explanatory, and for this to be the case there must be some explanatory framework within which the attribution is embedded - one cannot simply stipulate one’s way to explanation. To what extent does letting go of the word ‘knowledge’ signal an abandonment of the associated explanatory framework, intentional explanation?”

— Alex Barber, 2003, ‘Introduction’, in A. Barber (ed.), Epistemology of Language. Oxford; Oxford University Press, pp.10-11

 

To untie this knot of error, misunderstanding,…

 

(1) ‘Knowledge’ has not been “abandoned”. All of the surrogates, just like ‘knowledge’ itself, are informal terms. The surrogates were variously introduced because philosophers insisted, and still insist, on raising epistemological questions and complaints which were and remain irrelevant to the theoretical and empirical issues. If one has never been confused, then one should feel free to speak of ‘knowledge’. All of the surrogates are simply attempts to clarify the methodological point that linguistics concerns an internal state of the mind/brain. The attempts have proved to be curiously unsuccessful, as Barber goes on to exemplify.

 

(2) Barber suggests that employment of the surrogates might deflect from “the importance of reflecting on the character of the corresponding relatum”. It is difficult to see what Barber means. By the “relatum”, he can only mean UG or I-languages (in general, states of the language faculty); but it is absurd to suggest that the study of the language faculty has, in some sense, been neglected - linguistic theories are theories of the faculty, period. Further, it is a misnomer to think of the faculty as a relatum: as Chomsky makes clear (see the above quotations), a speaker/hearer isn’t externally related to the faculty; the faculty is a state of the speaker/hearer. A speaker can be said to be internally related to her language faculty, but such is a mere formal locution which, again, has no explanatory role to play.

 

(3) Barber takes it as given that “attributions of cognizing” are “explanatory, and for this to be the case there must be some explanatory framework within which the attribution is embedded - one cannot simply stipulate one’s way to explanation”. This thought is confused. Linguistic theories hypothesise that the mind/brains of ‘normal’ speaker/hearers realise certain complex states of a specific character; the theories don’t, nonsensically, attribute to speaker/hearers a cognizing of such states: speaker/hearers ‘cognize a language’, which means that their mind/brains are in particular states. ‘Cognize’ is a wholly informal term to signal that the mind/brain is our target; the term does no explanatory work at all. Barber’s remark about “stipulation” is a non sequitur whose provenance it would be tedious to explore.

 

(4) Barber asks “[t]o what extent does letting go of the word ‘knowledge’ signal an abandonment of the associated explanatory framework, intentional explanation?” This would be an interesting question if ‘knowledge’ were abandoned, or if there were an associated explanatory framework, or if such a framework were intentional. As it is, none of these conditions hold, or at least they don’t hold of linguistic theory.

 

 

A Conciliatory Coda: Two Options (Thanks to Guy Longworth)

 

(i) Epistemological/intentional concerns are hived off from the science proper. The science is ‘pure’, but there is no eliminativism.

 

This is a coherent response to the above arguments. The question arises, however, as to what one’s epistemology is of given that ‘language’ itself gives way to the faculty understanding…

 

(ii)  Intentional vocabulary might be indispensable to our achieving a ‘global view’ of how the language system relates to external systems and, ultimately, the speaker/hearer’s environment, including other persons.

 

Yes. Chomsky’s third characteristic of creativity is “appropriateness/coherence” of language use. This feature is indispensable to our conception of a language user, yet it falls outside of any scientific understanding; it is apparently dependent on our colloquial idioms for expression. Perhaps it always will remain so. However the facts may fall, here intentional vocabulary is a) not part of our theory proper and b) is not causally explanatory. It is the idiom which Skinner tried and failed to escape from. So much the worse for the causation of behaviour, and so much the worst for the idea that our folk conceptions are on scientific duty. (See Chomsky, 1966, Cartesian Linguistics, New York: Harper Row, pp.3-5; 1968/72, Language and Mind, New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, p.12.)