Critical notice: West's 'The American Evasion of Philosophy'

 

 

 

 

 

 

                                                                                                           Rupert J. Read

             

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

          ABSTRACT

 

     Critical Notice: West's 'The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism'

 

           West's book was conceived of as centrally focussed on the idea that a right understanding of the nature of Pragmatism, past and present, may be an integral component to contemporary American radical/progressive political struggles. This focus is evident in the framing of the book's narrative and its argument by its title, its introductory section, and its concluding section. I argue that, although this central idea of the book may well be right, West does not effectively realize its potential in his narrative and argument. In particular, he misreads the title of his own book, a title which points the way toward means of breaking more thoroughly with Analytic/epistemology-centred philosophy, in part perhaps through a closer alliance with certain strands in Continental philosophy (in both style and substance) than neo-Pragmatists tend to allow for.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Critical notice: C.West's 'The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism' [1]

 

     Five years or more after its publication, the initial flush of revies and praise having died down (and having been supplanted both by more recent productions of the author and his continuing rise in the public perception),we may be at about the right distance from it to appreciate both the worth of and the trouble with this important and already-influential work by Cornel West. This book ambitiously attempts to chronicle that lately-resurgent body of intellectual activity usually known as 'Pragmatism'. The below is not so much a book review as it is a review of the impact of the title-- 'The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism'.[2]

     Now by this I absolutely do not mean that what follows is an analysis of that nominative string, considered in isolation.[3] Rather, this article will be a sustained effort to consider some various possible meanings of this string; considered in the context first of the book by Cornel West which it names; second of that to which it refers -- namely Pragmatism, genealogised as an 'evasion' of Philosophy; and third of that with which it has, like any text, become inextricably intertwined -- namely, its scholarly and public reception. I shall argue that the body of the book named on the one hand, and the philosophy referred to on the other, are at times ill co-ordinated, and thus that a good deal is being missed if one's best account of the history of Pragmatism is this book  (To what degree and in what sense this might constitute a criticism will only become clear once we have considered what exactly it means to give a genealogy of something[4]). Thus by considering this title as synecdochal for its subject, I hope to suggest where future research on Pragmatism's past and present might usefully be aimed.

      There is a sense of the word "title" in which it is used synecdochally to mean that book which bears it (e.g. ''The University of Wisconsin Press has published 757 titles since 1989..."). It will be my suggestion that West may have missed two senses of his title and sub-title, senses which could have illuminated the subject-matter to which they refer. That such a failure to exploit the ambiguities of his chosen title may reveal a repression of a tradition(s) of philosophic and social thought which might have more of a claim on the future of (Prophetic) Pragmatism than West or other self-identified Pragmatists tend to allow. And, moreover, that this may be a clue to an apparent lack of writerly/textual self-consciousness or innovativeness in this (and other) works by West, to his sometime unawareness that this is a text, and that he has chosen to write it in a very particular way.

 

     Without further ado, let us turn to the title in question. The American...; we will let pass almost without comment the ubiquitous ethnocentric[5] use of the term, "American"; The American Evasion of Philosophy..., "evasion" is one of the two terms that these remarks will be concentrated on -- in what sense does West figure the authors he is reading to be evading Philosophy? Then the sub-title: A Genealogy..., "genealogy" is the second term I will be focussing on in detail; A Genealogy of Pragmatism -- in what sense is this a genealogy of Pragmatism?

     One further preliminary. The reader may already have noticed a certain degree of (perhaps) indecision with respect to c/Capitalization. I follow a convention of capitalizing when there is proper naming but also where one suspects reification.[6] Throughout West's text, he does not capitalize "evasion" or "genealogy" (they are capitalized on the front cover and the title page (unlike the word "of")). And his usage of 'p/Philosophy', 'p/Pragmatist' etc. is identical -- i.e. capital letters are used only in titles and headings.[7] There is perhaps thus a lost opportunity for nuance in distinguishing between, for instance, 'philosophy' the general activity, and 'Philosophy' the fach.

     This seemingly trivial thought brings us directly to the potentially important question of the non-standard -- and yet, limited -- senses that "evasion" and "genealogy" are supplied with in West's book on Pragmatism. And we can no longer avoid paying direct attention to those terms, as they figure in that text.

 

     In what sense(s) does West detail the American evasion of philosophy, via genealogising pragmatism?

     Well, his book is a narrative of the body of thought in action the title of which is due to Bain, Peirce and James (but whose 'pre-historical' beginning is fascinatingly traced back to Emerson) and progresses through Dewey to Neo-Pragmatism, via the leading 'mid-century pragmatic intellectuals' (Sidney Hook, C.Wright Mills, W.E.B.Du Bois, etc.). The inclusion of the latter group marks an important step away from conceiving of Pragmatism as narrowly Philosophical. Parts of the text yield as much discussion of social causes, and the effects of the inter-connecting views of these figures, as they do of those views, simpliciter. And the surprising omission of Mead[8] among others is perhaps justified by the constraints of the narrative format and of the book's slenderness.

     These points do not yet give us a sense of West's account as  singular, as altogether more politicised and historically-conscious than those of precursors, such as H.S.Thayer's.[9] Perhaps such is to be gleaned by attending further to West's bold title.

     Let us not avoid taking West's non-standard use (given the context, of philosophy) of "evasion" first, for it provides the most direct insight into this matter. Every evasion discussed in 'The American Evasion of Philosophy' is a valorized avoidance of an activity one had better not engage in, in short, of what is taken to be the "antiquated, anachronistic''[10] method and subject-matter of Modern philosophy. Kant had claimed with reference to his metaphysics that any philosopher:

 

     "...must satisfy the demands here made, either by adopting my solution or by thoroughly refuting it and substituting another. To evade it is impossible."[11]

 

           From Emerson, American Pragmatism begins, and from its beginnings, endeavours to evade Kant's demand. To quote from perhaps the richest and most resonant summation of what West means by 'evasion', by the 'evasion of philosophy':

 

      "To evade modern philosophy means to strip the profession of philosophy of its pretense, disclose its affiliations with structures of powers (both rhetorical and political) rooted in the past, and enact intellectual practices, i.e. produce texts of various sorts and styles, that invigorate and unsettle one's culture and society."[12]

 

           A fine evocation of a marvellous, multifarious 'program'; the question is whether or not West's text can be regarded as an adequate account of the history of that program(s), and/or as an instance, a continuation, of the 'evasion'. For while West is to some degree successful (unlike most of its other chroniclers) in not treating Pragmatism simply as a "..philosophical tradition putting forward solutions to perennial problems in the Western philosophical conversation initiated by Plato..."[13], it is not clear how sustained his 'evasion' of this model of philosophical historiography actually is.

     The phrase which is repeated on a myriad occasions in the course of the tale West tells, so much so that I hesitate before dwelling on it further, is the "..(Emersonian) evasion of (modern/epistemology-centred) philosophy.."[14]. 'Emerson'[15] and the 'evasion' he fostered are drummed into the reader, but without sufficient explication.

     Now it might be replied that West can simply assume the irony of invariably using the term ''evasion of modern philsophy" (and its cognates) affirmatively, of mocking the pretensions of the presently hegemonic form of Modern Western philosophy to be that which one should (like Truth...) pursue rather than evade. I apologise for a potential lack of subtlety in my interpretation of West -- perhaps others of his readers just read the alternative sense(s) of conjoing "evasion", "Philosophy" etc. straight into the silences of his text. However, one might justly find the gaps and silences greater than one might have hoped -- in finding West almost evasive when it comes to the significations of his title, and the substance of his subject-matter. An overabundance of understatement is risky.

     Let us then directly address alternative construals of the title under review. I have in mind two. The first appeals to a possible negative employment of "evasion", to make precisely the opposite point to that which West's book is intended to illustrate, and re-make. In short, this is the natural reading of West's title for a philosopher schooled in Analytic or Anglo-American orthodoxy -- that Pragmatism is precisely an evasion, a mere avoidance of Philosophy, and (thus) of serious thought. Could West not seriously have played with this point, to illumine the ideological breach between the thought-community of professionalized U.S. (Analytic) Philosophy and the loose family of pragmatists? In this case, it is the very same evasion of the very same Philosophy that is deplored by one party, and applauded by the other. I am suggesting that it would have done to have brought this out.

     The other alternative is perhaps the more interesting. It understands evasion negatively once more, but reads what has been evaded (by non-Pragmatists) as the 'general activity' of philosophising, with a distinctively small "p". In other words, this would be a reclamation of the claim of Emerson, Dewey, West et al to be truly (U.S.) philosophy, and not the orthodox, perhaps ersatz Philosophy which has, so some might claim, come to prevail across most of the U.S.A.. Thus construed, West's title has pragmatists assuming the mantle once more of genuinely leading U.S. cultural criticism, ethical thought, human reflection - philosophy. This is not necessarily to recommence a futile 'dialogue' of "We're the real philosophers!" "No, we are!" But it would involve holding it worthwhile to carry the banner of 'philosophy' forward into whatever successor-subjects one envisages. And after all, wasn't it something like this that Dewey had in mind when he entitled "...his seminal essay "The Need for a Recovery of Philosophy""?[16] (West might have wished not to endorse this sense of "philosophy" and its "evasion" due to a Marxian preference for "radical historicism" over and against "philosophy". But it is not clear that such a preference is compatible with a reliance upon the American intellectuals on which West's text centres -- of which, more below.)

     Interpolating the meaning that (judging by the body of his text) West most obviously wishes to impart to his title, we then have three readings of 'The American Evasion of Philosophy': as the orthodox Anglo-American take on Pragmatism's avoidance of (serious) Philosophy; as West's clever re-valuation of this evasion as an affirmative move; and as a re-considering of pragmatistic thought as actually and deeply philosophical in some important sense after all. (As noted, I do not find West either contesting or making use of either the first or the third of these readings.)

 

     And, fourthly, as being intrinsically related to the project(s) of Genealogy?[17] (Or) Is the sub-title of West's book noting that its author will bring to bear on the subject-matter referred to some technique(s) from a different tradition?

     In West's text, the word "genealogy"[18] features with far less frequency than any of the other words in the book's full title. In contrast to effusive reiteration of "the evasion of philosophy", in contexts which make it clear how West understands the phrase, the reader is given little by way of discussion, implicit or explicit, of the sense in which this work may be regarded as genealogical. Let us then ask in what sense this could be "a genealogy of pragmatism"?

     Uncontroversially, one could respond that West puts forth this book, as described above, as an account of the emergence, blooming and contemporary nature of the diffuse 'movement' known as Pragmatism. But could this be a genealogical account in the (Continental) philosophical sense of "genealogical" viz. in the sense in which Nietzsche, Foucault etc. have offered "genealogies"?[19] (That is, more than -- minimally -- being one possible account among many, as any Nietzschian genealogy must begin by recognising itself to be?[20])

     It is hard to see how it could, for it is in the nature of such genealogies to call into question, to 'unmask' that which is their subject. Whereas West is palpably not calling pragmatism into question in this sense - he does not see his subject in anything like the way the author of 'A Genealogy of Morals' saw his, as ripe for psycho-philosophical diagnosis and systematical suspicion. Or is he; does he? Is this a hint that the history and legacy of pragmatism are less certainly worthy of affirmation than West's text seems to want to claim, or at least that they require more critical re-assessment before or along with such affirmation?

     Certainly, elements of the latter are among some of the more important contributions that West's text makes to our understanding of Pragmatism, as for instance when he juxtaposes Emerson on Race with the purportedly democratic heritage of Pragmatic thought. There are moments in this work, then, when West does interrogate the vocabulary and the practice of Pragmatists, much as Nietzsche interrogates ascetic ideals, or as Foucault interrogates our meta-sexual or (more generally) surveillatory practices. Do we have to conclude that West is unmasking Pragmatism? No, this would have to be a gross misreading of the work as a whole. The alternative is as follows: we are forced to ask whether West may be pursuing a similar policy with regard to genealogising as he did in the case of evading, only in reverse. Is there an endeavour here to foment or cement a re-orientation of a term of (philosophic) discourse?

     But, in this case, what would be the point? For while valorising ''evasion of philosophy'' is one thing, is not taming the very notion of "genealogy" quite another? For while the former move is directed against 'the Right' (traditional Philosophy), the latter risks making a self-inflicted wound against 'the Left', putting in question the alliance between prophetic pragmatism on the one hand and "the continental travelling theories such as Marxism, structuralism, and poststructuralism"[21] on the other. In sum, West is caught in something of a dilemma; if he were to consistently follow a policy of, after Nietzsche or Foucault, genealogising Pragmatism, then he would risk alienating himself from Pragmatism; but if he does not consistently and evidently write such genealogy (as indeed he does not), then, again, how is this book living up to its title?

     One feels that the question, in what sense this book could possibly be a genealogy in the Nietzschian or Foucauldian sense of "genealogy", is indeed as urgent as Giles Gunn feels it to be, as he begins his study of Neo-Pragmatism with a section entitled ''In lieu of a genealogy of Pragmatism".[22] One seems drawn to conclude that, on pain of entering the mire just described, West is simply using the term "genealogy" straightforwardly in its dictionary, 'family-tree' sense (e.g. "Now if we study the genealogy of the James family, we will notice that Henry James's brother ..."). This interpretation is supported if we judge the book by (the illustration on) its cover, which envisions Pragmatism as the growth of a tree (with its roots wrapped around a great book), whose trunk is Emerson, whose major branches are Peirce and Dewey, and whose smaller branches are the various other great names of the Pragmatic philosphical and extra-philosophical tradition. And this evokes the irony, explored by Robert Gooding-Williams,[23] that although any philosopher's genealogy cannot avoid association with Foucault and Nietzsche, West's organismic account of Pragmatism's growth and essential continuity cannot, at least without some argument being given to the contrary, be regarded as a genealogy in anything other than this non-philosophical 'family-tree' sense. Such an organismic account is liable to harbour troubling telic elements, and to hide the themes of contingency and of our constructing our own history and future which must surely be central to a neo-Pragmatist account of Pragmatism's or of society's development. Any account which suggests a natural growth of the tree Emerson planted -- or that planted Emerson -- into Prophetic Pragmatism, or even of the inherent need of our society for such, is surely not credible in this historical moment. Pragmatism did not grow -- it was made, and it may or may not make itself part of the future of our society (rather than just of our philosophical community). Now, West must at some level be aware of this, for he makes his "highly selective interpretation of American pragmatism in light of the present state...of American culture" such as to provide "an interpretation of a progressive tradition that can inspire and instruct contemporary efforts to remake and reform American society and culture."[24] Thus we may be getting a little closer to a sense in which, at least implicitly, West's book is a genealogy after the Continental tradition: it was intended as and to some degree definitely reads as a piece of '(reading/writing) history as strategic intervention', and thus as a part of a (re-)making of Pragmatism.

     But the hypothesis I wish to entertain is this: that West may still be judged, to a not inconsiderable degree, to have actively forgotten the potential and multivalence of his sub-title, even more than of his title -- for he had somehow to explain or else to avoid explaining why Nietszche and Foucault (the 'originators' of genealogical method in philosophy and historiography) are actively written out of his Prophetic Pragmatism  (Also apparently forgotten is feminism, for it is noticeable that among the dozen figures West draws upon in situating his own Prophetic Pragmatism historically, there are no more women than there were in Jesus's Twelve[25]).

     Nietzsche, an inspiration for some neo-Pragmatists, creeps into the book at several points, but is mostly excluded by means of the (questionable, if increasingly popular) assumption that he was thoroughly anticipated by Emerson. This could only conceivably be correct if we have in mind a reading of Emerson on which he is a prophet of discontinuity, of the slippage of language etc.; but West's Emerson is largely a figure of and for stability and the beginnings of a continuity, encouraging West's readers "to conceptualize the pragmatist tradition as deriving its unity from a single vital potency."[26]

     The case of Foucault is even more instructive, for he is allotted a section of his own in the closing chapter of West's book.[27] And what eventuates in West's discussion of Foucault? Surprisingly, West misreads him not just 'creatively', but rather reductively-- he finds him nostalgic for Kantian transcendentalism, and thus insufficiently evasive of Philosophy. It is a reductive and dismissive misreading to find the kind of 'transcendence' that Foucault may have looked for to be simply Kantian in form for, as James Miller's intellectual biography of Foucault among others has carefully pointed out, Kant may have had a major influence on the French philosophe,but that could not possibly amount to an anticipation of Foucault's extraordinary focus on the historical and bodily processes of subjectification.[28]

     And further, West sees Foucault, as does Rorty,[29] as having absolutely nothing constructive to say about normative-political matters, only dystopian visions and warnings against trying to imagine any utopia. Why bring up the 'challenge' of Foucault, if only to abruptly dismiss it thus?[30] This is a treatment that West applies to no other of the dozen allotted their own sections in the course of his book; all are read more or less sympathetically and are allotted some kind of place in or near the Pragmatists' Pantheon. The punishment of Foucault by comparison smells of an active distancing, a sense of danger, a wish to forget ... to forget that someone who has read and taken seriously Nietzsche (and not just his American predecessor Emerson) would not have written a ''genealogy'' which largely 'evaded' the Nietzschian overtones of that word.

     The deep repugnance of Pragmatism for the Nietzschian tradition in Continental philosophising has deep roots, including of course a sense of their being in some respects similar, all-too-similar. Bernstein and Rorty among others have expressed in terms somewhat similar to West's the risks of choosing a ''Nietzschian'' (i.e. in their view overly radical and destructive) as opposed to a ''Hegelian'' perspective, for philosophers opposed to the Systematic ''Cartesian'' tradition.[31] Contemporary pragmatists appear to find it very hard to accept that there may be (transvalued) emancipatory value even in the political histories of Foucault. Yet a few pragmatistic thinkers have managed to do so, by reading Foucault more contextually and sympathetically -- e.g. Connolly, and Hacking.

     The immediate point here is this: Foucault, Paul Bové,[32] and a few others have given substance to the notion of writing history, particularly (but by no means exclusively) 'intellectual history', as genealogy, as one possible unmasking account of unpredictable and non-telic development which is not fascinated by the revelation of any originary or subsequent origin.[33] Along with certain other intellectual tools (including some of those recently in or near vogue under the name of 'New Historicism' or 'Cultural Poetics'), they have opened up a space for the writing of very different kinds of histories from those we have traditionally been used to -- sustainedly suspicious (yet not nihilistically pointless) self-consciously political histories (of the present[34]) of movementsfacilitating or embodying socio-political interventions, by hand or by brain -- just what West wanted his book to be.

     At this point, it might be objected that I am attending insufficiently to West's Gramscian leanings,[35]in attempting (e.g.) to impose too much "(European) travelling theory" on his strategically-motivated America-based theory. The objection would be that when, toward the very close of his book, West invokes Gramsci as an ally, he is making the case that, contra the 'Leninism' that would perhaps appear to offer the greatest possible consequences, one has deliberately to appeal effectively to the sensibilities of those one is concerned with organizing. Gramsci in his 'Prison Notebooks' argues that any insurgent political movement will have to be crafted using the indigenous cultural (and philosphical) resources at hand.

     However, the political praxis that West actually recommends is rather far from Gramsci's preference -- as is common among latter-day (non-Communist/Anarchist) 'Gramscians'.

     It should also be noted that, just as West insufficiently acknowledges the thoroughgoing complicity of some of his pragmatists (particularly, but not only, that "liberal" Cold Warrior, Reinhold Niebuhr[36]) with the dominant economic/political forces in the U.S. -- i.e. with the rapacious exploitation of the Third World, support for foreign dictators, ideological Anti-Communism, etc. -- so he fails to follow through on his purportedly Leftist heritage when he himself slips, once in a while, into the same mode as Niebuhr and the later Hook:

 

                "Yet principally owing to the tragic facts of survival, myopic leadership, and limited options, most third-world romanticism was diverted from the third wave of left romanticism into the traps of a regimenting Marxist-Leninism or a rapacious Americanism. The major exceptions -- Chile under Salvador Allende, Jamaica under Michael Manley, Nicaragua under the Sandinistas -- encounter formidable, usually insurmountable, obstacles. Needless to say, similar projects in second-world countries -- Hungary in 1956, Czechoslovakia in 1968, Poland in 1970 -- are tragically and brutally crushed." [37]

 

     The rhetorical contrast between the 'brutal crushing' of East European uprisings (which, "needless to say", is the work of the Soviet Union) on the one hand, and the nameless source of the ('natural'/'unavoidable'/'unfortunate'?) "diversion" of third world reformism and the "obstacles" to a third path on the other, is standard practice for establishment 'liberals/doves' in the U.S.A.; but one would have expected more of a democratic socialist (i.e. C.West). As has been shown by perhaps America's leading dissident intellectual today, Noam Chomsky, there is no serious historical issue as to the identity of this 'source' (of the crushing of those leftist experiments West claims to have the most sympathy for). Not to name it -- not to make quite plain the distinctively U.S. role in fomenting more than just the Pragmatists in the last one hundred years or so of world history -- is an unjustifiable evasion, of the facts.

 

     The word 'genealogy' is at or near the centre of the possibility of writing a history of a philosophical 'ism' which could make sense of that 'ism' by placing "..the leading figures...within a partial genealogy of their discursive and non-discursive practice";[38] and moreover by problematising the self-determination of any 'leading individuals', and emphasising their intellectual and practical indebtedness to various micro-social factors, including collectivities. For instance, mightn't Dewey's educational experiments, which of course were possible only with the creative input and activity of a body of people as well as of thought[39], be adjudged as significant a part of the history of Pragmatism as the publication of 'Democracy and Education' or 'Experience and Nature'?

     West, with Nancy Fraser, Anthony Appiah, and others on the intellectual Left, has rightly chided Richard Rorty for being too content in a self-proclaimed bourgeois democratic individualism, and for his Pragmatism thus having insufficient consequences, outside the discipline of Philosophy. As John Lyne has noted, "West seems to be exhorting Rorty to a heartier style of social critique, toward "genealogical accounts deployed as moral and political weapons"".[40] But what none of West's commentators have managed to do is to demonstrate how he can retain the right to usefully term his own work a 'genealogy'. Rorty's influential shadow is already a long one, and it perhaps requires more 'non-American' resources than West allows himself to employ in order to swerve out of its reach. West has successfully refused to write a reductionistic account of Pragmatism as merely an instrument of bourgeois reaction; why did he not strive more strongly also to refuse to write an account that remains essentially a quasi-Bloomian story of strong 'paternal' thinkers? An overall problem with West's book is that at the level of methods (and even of genre) it is not evident that the marvellous hopes immanent in its title and evident in its Introduction are realised,[41] and thus one might incline toward the conclusion that "West's pragmatism, like Rorty's, is likely to remain a pragmatism without consequences."[42]

     I have already explained this in respect of the title. In the  Introduction of 'The American Evasion of Philosophy', one is given some reason to hope that West will deliver, as he writes of..

 

      "..American pragmatism as a specific historical and cultural product of American civilization, a particular set of social practices that articulate certain American desires, values, and responses that are elaborated in institutional apparatuses principally controlled by a significant slice of the American middle-class."[43]

 

      And again, as he rightly claims that..

 

     "..with Dewey...American Pragmatism achieves intellectual maturity, historical scope, and political engagement. In this sense my genealogy of American pragmatism is an explicitly political interpretation..."[44]

 

     But West does not deliver what he prophesises; in part, for reasons already given. In addition to these, it is salient in this connection to note that -- like Rorty, whose work he (critically) assumes and resumes[45] -- West is typically Pragmatist in writing antiphilosophical philosophy  in nonphilosophical language only to the (not insignificant) extent of not conforming to the Anglo-American norm of utilising a quasi-technical vocabulary in order explicitly to make arguments to (philosophical) conclusions. That is, Rorty and West otherwise read much as any other 'Analytic' philosopher -- there is none of the supra-literary innovativeness of Derrida or Irigaray, or the dense 'diagrammatic' approach of Deleuze or Foucault, or the intricate criss-crossing later Wittgensteinian technique. West's writing in the book under consideration here, (or Rorty's in 'Contingency, irony and solidarity', in the course of which Rorty enthusiastically endorses precisely such Continental innovativness) is arguably much more similar stylistically to J.Fodor's or B.Williams's than to Foucault's, or Wittgenstein's. This is truly a problematic self-referential irony for both West and Rorty -- for Pragmatists, unlike 'mainstream' Analytics, cannot try to appeal to the alibi of writing 'neutrally', or without a particular style.[46] In short, even if style and method are in some sense separable, West is arguably no more differentiable from Rorty at the level of style[47] than he is at the level of method. This is one of several reasons for believing that West has broken with 'Philosophy' (or contributed to a link in its evolution) less substantially or consequentially than he wishes.

     It might be objected, to continue the 'Gramscian' line commenced above, that it is precisely in respect of style and method that West is savviest, because most appealing to American sensibilities. He thus has some hope of marshalling (the local) philosophical resources needed to catalyze political and cultural change. (According to Rorty, philosophy can have little such role, though he insists that the Pragmatists provide sufficient resources for those (e.g. Feminists) who might be aided by the tools of philosophers' deflationary critique(s).[48]) According to West, perhaps, philosophers' role(s) here can be not insignificant, but for American philosophers to speak in the idiom of M.Foucault would be too jarring. Foucault -- like Lenin in 1920s Italy -- would be too 'foreign' and would clash with rather than cleave to the culture one is trying to change. As Gramsci suggests, and West perhaps evidences, it is better to be a quasi-nationalist, and (thus) forward one's program as effectively as possible. The organic intellectual may have to muck about in political compromises and engage in some philosophic slight of hand, but concrete consequences may result. The academic intellectual may be at the vanguard of the APA, but otherwise unintelligible, inconsequential.

     This is potentially a real objection to my argument, and it makes clear that, even if West comes up short on "evasion" and "genealogy", there may still be practically pressing options concerning which his line in the title under review calls for close attention. A full response would take us too far afield. In my judgement, however, the criticisms of West already made above (e.g. around the very idea of "America", and his sometimes brittle leftist credentials), combined with a close examination of the perhaps dangerous habits of minds behind the very idea of such notions as "the American habit of mind", and with a reiteration of the vital Foucauldian critique of "organic intellectualism" (taking seriously the alternatives to it that Foucault described and exemplified) would suffice to largely rebut it; but this must be for the reader to decide.

 

     In the wake of these criticisms it is salient to re-iterate that West's book [49] is definitely worth reading, and acting upon. That this is so is, one might say, because it does realize at least some of the promise of its quite wonderful title, and Introduction.

     And so West's is truly an achievement, to have managed to combine philosophy and critical history to the extent that 'The American Evasion of Philosophy' has done; for others have generally only managed one or the other. For instance, Thayer's massive study never shows a serious effort to comprehend Pragmatism socio-politically; and Thayer's account is not less interested in non-discursive and other historical features of Pragmatism than most others. Most narratives on the topic have been primarily intellectualist, even narrowly philosophical; while those which have taken history or politics seriously (particularly in the form of concrete social interventions) have in general lacked philosophical nuance. This is an irony which should not be lost on any familiar with the deeply Deweyan antipathy toward separation between theory and practice, between ideas and their contexts.

     Yet the irony seems partly lost even on Morton White, that insightful and most prodigious of recent philosopher-chroniclers of Pragmatism.[50] My point in this critical notice is ultimately the following: West has succeeded more than anyone else in pointing out how and where a contemporary understanding of Pragmatism should be headed, and even in writing its history of and for the present, a history which is not only that of successive philosophical positions. That he should have done so is inevitably of particular noteworthiness, given his seemingly ever-increasing visibility as a standard-bearer for the intellectual/activist Left. Perhaps, however, while swerving away from the Analytic paradigm which has attempted to find in philosophy's history only the history of ever-improving arguments over narrowly-definable problems, West has lost sight of certain problematic features of both narrowly philosophical and historico-political histories of ideas, features which are not absent from his account.

     Let us now look toward an account of Pragmatism which will be worthy of all the words we find on the cover of West's book. Such an account would methodologically consider the spoken as well as the written word, the non-linguistic as well as the linguistic action, and it would strive harder not to consider writings abstracted from their socio-historical contexts and from the material category changes that mould such contexts. Still less would it consider only individuals-- Pragmatism is, as West well explains, a different kind of philosophy if it is philosophy at all, and it requires a different accounting to be given of itself. Pragmatists can learn from feminists, who tend to conceptualise theoretical and empirical developments more socially (though hardly impersonally).

     Such a re-reading/re-writing would eventuate not only in a Pragmatism with consequences, but in a Pragmatism genuinely open both to Foucault and Feminisms, to reading its own history more self-critically aware, in particular, of its historic determinants and blindnesses. West does a stunning job of re-reading Pragmatism in respect of Race and to some extent in respect of Class -- I look forward to the same being true of a future work in respect of, for instance, Nationality and Gender too, such that West's goal of including those unjustly excluded from (accounts of) this movement, in the past or in the present, might be more fully satisfied. A genealogy, neither organismic nor individualistic, should be able "to evade the narrative myth of 'America'",[51] and perhaps to speak more concretely to the hearts and minds of women, of non-U.S. citizens, and (at length, even) of non-philosophers. And one can perhaps risk prophesising that we then might just see a Pragmatism not only re-surgent but also in-surgent.[52]

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

WORKS CITED

 

 

Ayer, A.J. . 1968.  The Origins of Pragmatism.  San Francisco: Freeman Cooper.

 

Bové, Paul.  1986. Intellectuals in Power: A genealogy of critical humanism.   New York:                                                                          Columbia U. Press.

 

Chambliss, J.J. .  1993.  "On the claim that Dewey's educational theories were not put                                                                      into practice by Dewey."  (Forthcoming)

 

Chomsky, Noam. 1988. Manufacturing Consent. (With Edward Herman). New York:                                                                                                            Pantheon Books.

                            1992. Deterring Democracy. New York: Hill and Wang.

 

Deleuze, Gilles.  1986.  Foucault.  (Transl. and ed. by Hand, Minnesota: U.Minn., 1988).

 

Dewey, John.  1920.  Reconstruction in Philosophy.  New York: Henry Holt &Co. .

 

Dreyfus and Rabinow.  1982.  Michel Foucault: beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics.                                                                        Chicago: Chicago U.Press.

 

Foucault, Michel.  1971.  "Nietzsche, Genealogy, History'' .   (Transl. by Bouchard and                                                                                  Simon (1977))  In Foucault's  Language, Counter-memory,                                                                      Practice.  Ithaca: Cornell.

"    "    "    ".  1977.  Discipline and Punish: The birth of the prison (transl. A.Sheridan).                                                                                New York: Pantheon Books.

 

Gramsci, Antonio.  1971 (posthumous). Selections from the Prison Notebooks.  (Ed. and                                                                               transl. by Hoare and Nowell- Smith.)  New York: International.

 

Green, Judith.  Forthcoming.  "King's Pragmatic Philosophy of Political                                                                                                                                              Transformation." Journal of Social Philosophy.

 

Grossman, Morris.  1991.  "Book Review: The American Evasion of Philosophy".                                                                                                                          Canadian Phil. Quarterly, December 1991, pp.434-6.

 

Gooding-Williams, Robert.  1991.  "Evading narrative Myth, Evading Prophetic                                                                                                                                    Pragmatism: C.West's The American Evasion of Philosophy".

                                     The Massachussetts Review, Vol.32 no.4, pp.517-542.

 

Gunn, Giles.  1992.  In the American Grain.  Chicago: U.Chicago Press.

 

Hacking, Ian.     1990.  "Two kinds of "New Historicism" for Philosophers". New                                                                                                                              Literary History, Vol.21 no.2, pp.343-364.

     

Hayakowa, S.I. .  1968.  Choosing the right word.   New York: Harper & Row.

 

Kant, Immanuel.   1783.  Prolegomena to any future metaphysics. (Transl. by                                                                                                                       J.Ellington (1977))  Indianapolis: Hackett.

 

Kripke, Saul. 1980.  Naming and Necessity. Oxford:Blackwell.

 

Lang, Berel. 1990.  The Anatomy of Philosophical Style.   Oxford: Blackwell.

 

Lovibond, Sabina.  1992.  "Feminism and Pragmatism: A reply to Richard Rorty". New                                                                           Left Review 193.

 

Lyne, John.  1990.  "The Culture of Inquiry". Quarterly Journal of Speech76                                                                                                                             pp.192-224.

 

Miller, James.  1993.  The Passion of Michel Foucault.  New York: Simon and Schuster.

 

Murphy, John.  1990.  Pragmatism: from Peirce to Davison.  Boulder, CO: Westview    

                                       Press.

 

Novak, George.  1975.  Pragmatism Versus Marxism.  New York: Pathfinder.

 

Putnam, Hilary. 1993. Renewing Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

 

Rorty, Richard.  1979.  Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature.  Princeton: Princeton                         

                                       U.Press.

"    "    "      "   .   1986.  "Foucault and Epistemology" (pp.41-50 of Hoy (ed.), 'Foucault:                                                                                      A critical reader.   Oxford: Blackwell).

"    "    "     "   .  1989.   Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity.  Cambridge: Cambridge                                                                                                                                 U.Press.

"     "    "     "  .  1990 (Dec. 8).  "Feminism and Pragmatism", The Tanner Lecture,                                                                                                                                      Univ.. of Michigan.

"    "    "     "   .  1992.  "Moral Identity and Private Autonomy" (pp.328-333 of                                                                                                                                                 Armstrong (ed. and transl.), Michel Foucault, philosophe.                                                                                  NY:Routledge).

 

Rouse, David.   1993.   "Book Review" of Cornel West, The Ethical Dimensions of                                                                                                                                Marxist Thought.  Radical Philosophy Review of Books, Number                                                                  7, pp.14-17.

 

Rucker, Darnell.  1969.  The Chicago Pragmatists.  Mineapolis: U.Minnesota.

 

Sax, B.C. .  1991.  "On the Genealogical method: Nietzsche and Foucault".  International                                                                               Studies in Philosophy, Vol.xxii no.2.

 

Stack, George.   1992.  Nietzsche and Emerson: An elective affinity.  Chicago: Ohio                                                                                                                             U.Press.

 

Stern, David.   1995.   Wittgenstein on Mind and Language.  Oxford: O.U.P. .

 

Thayer, H.S. .  1968.  Meaning and Action: A critical history of Pragmatism.                                                                                                                                      Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

 

Wells, Harry K. .  1954.  Pragmatism, Philosophy of Imperialism.  Freeport, NY: Books                                                                     for Libraries Press.

 

West, Cornel. 1989.  The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism'.                                                                               Madison, WI: U. Wisconsin Press.

"   "    "     " .  1990.  "The limits of neo-pragmatism". South California Law Review,                                                                                                                       Vol.63, n.6.

"   "    "     " .  1993.  Beyond Eurocentrism and Multiculturalism.  Monroe, ME: Common  

                                   Courage Press.

 

Westbrook, Robert.  1991.  John Dewey and American Democracy.  Ithaca: Cornell.

 

White, Morton.  1956. Toward Reunion in Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard U.Press.

 "      "      "     ".   1973. Pragmatism and the American Mind. New York: Oxford U.Press.

"      "      "     ".   1976. Social Thought in America: The revolt against Formalism.                                                                                                                                    London: Oxford U.Press.

 

Wiener, Phillip.  1973.   "Pragmatism".  Pp.551-570  in his Dictionary of the History                                                                                      of Ideas.  New York: Charles Scribner's Sons. 

 



[1] Full bibliography appended. I wish to acknowledge, besides a couple of very helpful anonymous reviewers, the participants in a talk (from which this paper has grown) given to the Phil. Dept. at the U. of Houston, June 5 '92, and to the Phil. Dept. at Rutgers U., NJ, Dec.2 '92, entitled ''Three Pragmatists? -- West, Stich, Goodman''; particular thanks go to A.Jacobson, C.Freeland, and also to S.Fitzgerald and A.de Vivo, without whom this would never have been written.

[2]Following in the spirit of Colin McGinn's teaching method -- he once claimed to teach an entire course on the title Naming and Necessity...

[3]It would be an enterprise in absurdity to try to make sense of a non-sentential string; and without reference to its (linguistic and extra-linguistic) context(s).

[4]See West (1989), p.6.

[5]R.Rorty attempts to rewrite 'ethnocentricity' without negative connotations -- but try telling a Latin American there are no strings attached to the unproblematised appropriation by U.S. citizens of the appellation 'American'. It is ironical that West does not display more sensitivity to this (even when discussing the work of Roberto Unger), for he does touch on the question of U.S. ethnocentrism on p.5 and pp.32-3 of the title under review. Here is a concrete political consequence of a Rortian  endeavour philosophically to de-problematise 'ethnocentrism'.

[6]Cf. Rorty on philosophy and Philosophy, in Rorty, (1979). And Sabina Lovibond on this treatment of the "fetishistic capital letter", on p.59 of her (1992).

[7]In fact, the only one of his titular terms not to be consistently lower-cased in the text itself is -- revealingly? -- 'american'. See note 5, above; but also see n.9 on p.140 of Berel Lang, (1990). lang suggests that it is an act of Neo-Pragmatist nominalism to refuse capitalization except to begin a sentence with...

[8]One account implying the indispensability of Mead to a Pragmatism encompassing more than just Philosophy is Darnell Rucker's (1969). Can one evade Philosophy without attending closely to its successors in the domains of education, psychology, and politics? One's thoughts turn (contra West, on p.235 of his (1989)) to M.L.King Jr.,  who, J.Green argues in the Journal of Social Philosophy (forthcoming), held "[A] Pragmatic Philosophy of Political Transformation".

[9]Meaning and Action: A critical history of Pragmatism (1968). This thorough work anticipates West's book in some respects (without being mentioned by the latter).

[10]West, (1989), p.36.

[11]Preface to (1783), p.9.

[12]West, (1989), p.37.

[13]Ibid., p.5.

[14]Ibid.; vida, e.g., p.4, p.5, p.36, p.37, p.42, p.49, p.53, etc.. Does West's adding "evasion", re-valued, to our philosophical vocabulary, really abett his project; as oppposed to (say) a more extended exposition on his part of the relation of evading philosophy to a Deweyan overcoming of philosophical dichotomies?  The phrase, "(Emersonian/Deweyan) culture of creative democracy" is also frequently repeated, without much explanantion at all. Might creative democracy's nature not be considered in greater depth by contrast with the Niebuhr/Lippmann alternative (as documented by R.Westbrook, in Parts 3 & 4 of his (1991), and in effect by N.Chomsky, scatteredly throughout his corpus); or of just how, concretely, the prophetic pragmatist should pursue 'creative democracy' in the contemporary North. With regard to the latter, West is unforthcoming in The American...; probably he would appeal to his other/future work, including more directly political acts of writing (and activism), such as his (1993).

[15]On West's synechdocal reliance on 'Emerson' tropologicaly or as a myth of origins for Pragmatism, see R.Gooding-Williams's (1991). This piece lays out the ironies of thus employing the proto-Nietzschian Emerson as the 'roots' of a quasi-organic movement -- one which one is supposedly genealogising; cf. note 23, below.

[16]West, (1989), p.87. Compare Dewey's evocative call for Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920); also Hilary Putnam's for Renewing Philosophy (1993).

[17]The key specification of a genealogical project is Foucault's 'seminal' essay, (1971).

[18]On the back dust jacket of West's book, "genealogy" appears in scare quotes, just thus. Someone disinclined to use the term 'genealogy' except in its 'family-tree' sense might of course want to question whether Pragmatism was/is really the kind of 'family' that one could usefully describe the tree of... . In his "The limits of Neo-Pragmatism" (1990), a supporting article to his book, West strangely writes of his book being a "genealogy on pragmatism" (p.1749, my italics).

[19]Non-reductive exegetical accounts of what exactly this comes to are surprisingly hard to come by; the best three are perhaps those given by B.C.Sax, (1990), although Sax tends rhetorically to over-estimate the discontinuity between Nietzschean and Foucauldian Genealogy; by Dreyfus and Rabinow, in early chapters of their (1982); and by Paul Bove (cf. note 32, below).

[20]See again p.6f. of West's book.

[21]Ibid., p.239.

[22]In the American Grain, (1992).

[23]Gooding-Williams (1991), especially pp.519-521. He draws on Poirier to argue, as I also suggest below, that it is not Pragmatistic to argue against the Nietzschian tradition here, that to do so misses the instability of language. See note 26, below.

[24]West (1989), pp.6-7.

[25] More tellingly, the eleven or so contemporary American pragmatists West mentions (including the nine on p.3) are all men. He addresses the apparent paucity of women (pp.180-1) thus: "I suspect that American culture, with its Emersonian individualism, and pragmatist experimentalism, cuts deeper than sexual identity. If so, the issue is how American women will reshape and revise pragmatism...". Indeed; but he might have mentioned women who arguably are already doing just that, such as the likes of Nancy Fraser, Annette Baier, Joan Williams, even (more recently) Gayatri Spivak.

[26]Gooding-Williams (1991), p.519.  Organicism and genealogy are simply not compatible -- here is a respect in which Emerson did not anticipate Nietzsche  (This is not substantively contested by G.Stack, in his (1992)). Incidentally, backing my stress on West's repetitions, Gooding-Williams's quote begins thus: "[I]t is West's rhetorical repetition of the name "Emerson"...that more than any of the rhetorical strategies he otherwise employs encourages his readers to ...".

[27]West (1989), pp.223-226: ''The challenge of Michel Foucault''.

[28]Miller (1993); cf. particularly chapters 9 and 10. It would take us too far afield here to substantiate these points; but my point is that West's own brief discussion is hardly sufficient to substantiate the wildly novel view (which is not shared by any other neo-Pragmatists, to my knowledge) that Foucault is not radical enough in his break with traditional epistemology-centred philosophy's methods and conclusions.

[29]Particularly in his (1992). Rorty explains his distrust of 'Nietzschian' contemporaries such as Foucault in his (1986).

[30]Miller (1993) is even more useful in this respect, bringing out several phases in Foucault's evolution as a political philosopher (though he overplays Foucault's late enthusiasm for liberalism in his discussions of 'governmentality' -- see pp.299-312).

[31]These terms are from Rorty, (1986).

[32]Intellectuals in Power: A genealogy of Critical Humanism. The importance of Bové's account in this context is that, while he too is generally deeply sympathetic to the philosophes (and their projects and movements) which he is attempting to genealogise, he succeeds more than West in critically interrogating the humanism of these oppositional intellectuals, and arguably also in placing them historico-culturally. He details how Foucault was neither the "organic intellactual" he criticised nor, contra West (on p.225 of his (1989)), a "specific intellectual", but something in between. And compare his vivid Foreword to G.Deleuze's Foucault, (1988).

[33]Thus not a 'diagnosis' of Pragmatism as simply the philosophy of Capitalism/Imperialism (see Harry K.Wells (1954), and George Novak (1975)), nor simply a 'history of (philosophical) ideas' account, of which there have been many (compare for instance Phillip Wiener's (1973), or A.J.Ayer's (1968)), but a genealogyof (a non-Essentialized) Pragmatism. More on what exactly the latter would mean is to be found in Gooding-Williams's (1991), particularly at p.520.

[34]This redolent phrase is from p.31 of Foucault, (1977).

[35]See especially pp.230-2.

[36]Contrast (e.g.) p. 253, p.365, and p.371 of Chomsky's (1992) with the friendly treatment Niebuhr receives at West hands on (e.g.) p.163 and p.228 of his (1989). Cf. note 14, above.

[37]West (1989), pp.218-9. It is important to acknowledge that there are some perhaps countervailing moments in; e.g. on p.122 and p.162.

[38]Bové, (1986), p.10. However, one should note that the one thing which Bové does not really succeed in doing any better than West is to succeed in turning the focus away from considering 'leading figures' to considering the discipline or the 'ism' in question as a partially unified, partially contested collectivity of subjects (and their inter-relations).

[39]See J.Chambliss's ''On the claim that Dewey's educational views were not put into practice by Dewey" (forthcoming); and Westbrook (1991), passim.

[40]John Lyne, p. 202 of his (1990); the nested quote is from The American... .

[41]Lang's (1990) sufficiently defines "genre", "method" and "style" for my purposes.

[42]Gooding-Williams,(1991), p.537.

[43]West, (1989), p.4.

[44]Ibid., p.6. This politicality of the work is a strength and, as mentioned earlier, partially supports a claim to its being a genealogy; I am claiming however that the reach of the claim is deeper than (that of) the work. There are various -- partially political -- questions around one's genre, method and style that West fails adequately to answer.

[45]Compare the aphorism prefacing The American Evasion of Philosophy: ""Pragmatists keep trying to find ways of making anti-philosophical points in nonphilosophical language" - R. Rorty."

[46]This point is structurally the same as that made by Gary Shapiro in his ironising commentary on Berel Lang's ''The style of method'', presented Dec. 29 1991 at the APA Eastern Division Conference, N.Y.C., in which he demonstrated that Lang's practice contradicted his dictum that "style is largely constitutive of method". Lang's general perspective here remains useful, because he does at least take unusually seriously the 'literary' elements of philosophical writing.

[47]Form/style is a crucial aspect of what non-philosophers (e.g. social or literary critics) get out of philosophy; this is arguably a respect in which Rorty and West remain 'philosophers' philosophers' in the Anglo-American tradition, with a quasi-New York Review of Books style. This point may not be restricted in import to intra-academic politics, any more than were Marx's style and methods.

[48]See his (1990).

[49]Others have criticised it far more severely, and too unsympathetically. For instance, M.Grossman in a Review, slams it as, "a part of a body of writing that belongs to the very highest levels of intellectual elitism..." (1991, p.436), on account of West's perhaps over-zealous hopes for its socio-political  impact.

[50]White understands Pragmatism less narrowly than most philosophers, yet his work does not match West's in the level of its political consciousness. See White (1956), (1973), (1976).

[51]Gooding-Williams, (1991), p.532.

[52]I believe that White's, Westbrook's and West's works point clearly to the reality of these possibilities, even if (as yet) they do not realize them. As West has written, at the close of a sympathetic critique of a fellow prophetic pragmatist (Jefrey Stout), "Needless to say, he would have had to write another and different kind of book to do what I request" (pp.177-8 of his (1993)).