The ghost of Winch’s ghost: On primitive misunderstandings of philosophers

 

The Idea of a Social Science and its Relation to Philosophy is a polemical work. Peter Winch wrote it when he was less than 30. It is the text of an angry young man -- of someone angry at the potentially-dangerous perspective(s) on society dominant in his time ... and still, I would suggest, dominant (albeit mostly in different guises) today.

            A sober assessment of Winch’s challenge and achievement in the philosophy of the social sciences, after his death and at a distance of over 40 years from his original text, will take seriously into account both what it was that he wished polemically to question and challenge, and what it was that he himself actually wanted to say. On the latter front especially, a serious effort to understand Winch will take into account how he wished to be heard and read, in the light of the ‘evidence’ which the totality of his later work provides.

            In particular, I think that one if one can must re-read The Idea of a Social Science in the light of the ‘Preface’ which Winch added in 1990. If one can, because an author suggesting how their own work should be understood cannot be guaranteed to get it right, especially when writing much later. Authorship is not a trump card; but it is, I think, a card to which attention should always be closely paid. If one wants to understand a text, rather than reductively misread it or fail to read it altogether, then one will want if possible to understand it as its author understands it. (Where the text is simply confused, or where the author is evidently revising the text rather than exegetically commenting on it, then one will of course have to give up such a strategy.[1] )

            Few indeed of the many critiques of Winch written over, say, the last decade, take Winch’s post-1964 [2] work at all seriously. The special issue of this journal recently devoted to Winch’s work is no exception. This special issue features ten papers, by some major names in the field. It features several authors who would characterize themselves as ‘Wittgensteinians’ of one stripe or another. It contains several papers which purport to involve a serious effort at understanding Winch. Some of the papers in it are interesting, and there is some good philosophical and intellectual work in them. But my own opinion is that, regrettably, at most two of them actually succeeds in taking up a Wittgensteinian stance upon the human and social sciences.[3] That at most the same two of them succeeds in understanding Winch in a manner that Winch himself I think would find minimally acceptable. In sum, that hardly any of them takes up the kind of anti-theoreticist stance that I believe Winch followed Wittgenstein in taking.

            Most of the papers, of course, mean to criticise Winch in one or another fashion. But I believe that they mostly fail even to do that. Because they do not evince a sufficient level of understanding of what they are intending to criticise. So the criticisms are largely directed against a ghost of Winch’s ghost, not against his actual work or its actual spirit.

            “But what”, asks an interlocutor, “do you mean by ‘theory’ or ‘theoreticist’? You say that we argue only against a ghostly unreal Winch; but what would it be to take up a non-theoretical stance vis-a-vis the social sciences? Isn’t the avoidance of theory itself merely an out-dated empiricist fantasy? And isn’t it only Winch’s empiricist fantasy of natural science[4] that stands against what he calls ‘social study’ so as to provide a supposedly clear counter-class?”

            It is true that Winch’s 1958 presentation was marred by an empiricist rendering of natural science. Here are Winch’s words on the topic from 1990:

 

[Insert Preface quote]

 

            The question as to what it would be to take up a non-theoretical stance in reflection (e.g.) upon ‘the social sciences’ is a good question. But those asking it often seem to think it a rhetorical question, a question that answer itself in the following way: it is impossible for there to be any such stance. The claim that a non-theoretical stance in philosophy is impossible is a claim that I must question. I might ask, first, what is it that is being said to be impossible here? Until that question is answered, my interlocutor’s own claim is moot -- what is being claimed?[5] It often seems that such a ‘claim’ is a product of what Richard Rorty [6] has denominated ‘post-modern knowingness’. According to such a ‘knowing’ stance, ‘everyone’ knows in advance that anyone claiming to be able to

do without a theory is merely relying tacitly and dishonestly on a (hidden) theory. Often, such ‘knowingness’ is in the service not of a genuine anti-positivism, but of a elitist politicising theoreticism.

            The point of much of the best work on and after Wittgenstein in the last generation has been to dispute such assumptions. More specifically, there is a ‘school’ of Wittgensteinians (loosely associated with the heritage of Winch, more closely with that of Cavell and Diamond,[7]  gathered most conveniently in my collection, The New Wittgenstein), who believe that Wittgenstein can be understood, after his own word, as no purveyor of theories, or of any philosophical assertions or theses barring those which elicit no disagreement. The scholars in this ‘school’ dispute that the ‘return to the everyday’ need be conservative politically;[8] they dispute that it need be naive philosophically;[9] and they ask (again) whether the very various philosophical and social theoretic opponents of the everyday have in fact succeeded in saying anything at all, when they say that such a return is ‘impossible’.

            Martin Stone’s essay “Wittgenstein and Deconstruction” examples the last of these points particularly well. Stone notes the deep similarities of influential currents in recent English-speaking philosophy -- for example Saul Kripke’s work on ‘rule-scepticism’ -- to the influential current in Continental philosophy explicitly known as ‘Deconstruction’. (‘Deconstructive’ writing typically suggests that there is no escape from the ‘trap’ of language, that one should be anti-metaphysical but yet that there is no escape from metaphysics, that everything is political -- examples of the spirit of ‘Post-Modern knowingness’.) Stone then tries to understand what Derrida can be trying to say in his ‘Deconstructive’ writings (N.B. Stone here practices what this school preaches -- namely, an attempt to understand, rather than to dismiss as more ‘positivistic’ readers of Wittgenstein have tended to do.[10] ). Stone notes carefully Derrida’s own painstaking efforts to avoid the clichés of Post-Modern knowingness. But he reluctantly concludes, even so, that he cannot find a successful way of understanding what Derrida is trying to say, and in particular that Derrida has not shown that there does not exist a way of dealing with philosophical perplexities which refrains from giving a philosophical account or theory, or making philosophical claims (see Stone, p.106). In short, Stone argues (on p.84) that “a central aim of Wittgenstein’s discussion [of rules] is to suggest that if (1) a certain metaphyiscal idea of meaning and (2) the deconstruction of that idea seem to exhaust the philosophical options, that is owing to our failure to see another possibility -- namely, a return to the ordinary or everyday: “What we do [i.e. in contrast to other philosophers -- Stone’s note] is to bring words back from their metaphysical to their everyday use.” [PI para.116]  Wittgenstein identifies philosophy’s metaphysical voice as his critical target. But this alone would hardly distinguish him from any number of other philosophers within the huge Kantian wake of philosophy’s self-criticism. So it would be a mistake to infer, from such a common metaphysical target, that the contrast Wittgenstein wishes to draw (between himself and others) should not embrace -- or even refer most especially to -- those philosophers who [like Derrida] set their face against metaphysics. “We bring words back`’ -- Wittgenstein is to be read as saying -- “in contrast to the way other philosophers criticize metaphysics; in their form of criticism, words remain metaphysically astray.””

            So: the school of ‘New Wittgensteinians’ associated particularly with Cavell and Diamond holds, as we have argued now in some considerable detail elsewhere, that it is possible to interpret Wittgenstein as austerely non-theoretical, and as resolutely therapeutic in his philosophical aims and methods. We take seriously moments in Wittgenstein such as the following (and we regard these moments not as naive retreats into ‘common-sense philosophy’ or empiricism, but as reminders of a possibility undreampt of in Analytic or empiricist or Post-Modernist philosophies):

 

“We may not advance any kind of theory. There must not be anything hypothetical in our conisderations. We must do away with all explanation, and description alone must take its place.” [11]

 

I believe that the main currents in Winch’s thought are consonant with the ‘New Wittgenstein’ interpretation. That is why this ‘detour’ into Wittgenstein’s thought was necessary -- it is no detour.[12] After Winch, after Wittgenstein, I am against anything probably worth calling ‘theory’ in the social studies in most cases for the following reasons:

1) ‘Theory’ in the social studies tends to occlude the very phenomena it deals with, substituting for them simplified ‘dummy’ versions;

2) Part of this process is an abstraction from participants’ own understandings which, when it is deep or complete,[13] fails to deal with those participants as humans or social actors at all.

3) Explanatory theories distract us from the real task of assembling therapeutically-motivated descriptions of certain social phenomena which DO puzzle us.

            The last of these was especially Winch’s concern.

            But it is worth issuing provisos such as that it is perhaps only ‘in most cases’ that theory-talk is to be avoided in (the philosophy of) social study, because my position here is not dogmatic. I do not say that there cannot be uses of the word ‘theory’ in relation to activities of social study which are intelligible and helpful; I say that the word has a bad history in this context, and is probably best avoided. I do not say that whether or not one calls what one is doing the production of a theory or not is the key issue; on the contrary, it is at most a marker of more fundamental issues concerning the character of one’s intellectual work. I say that most intellectual work which pretends to the production of or the realisation of something like what has been traditionally called a social theory (whether an ‘old’ social theory (e.g. ‘Scientific Socialist’ class-analysis) or a ‘critical social theory’ (e.g. Giddens’s or Bhaskar’s)) is highly likely to be vulnerable to the criticisms that I have mentioned and that Winch was the first to explore in detail.

            Nigel Pleasants’s book Wittgenstein and the idea of a critical social theory buttresses the last of my claims here. Pleasants’s allusion to Winch in his title is to the point: the point of Pleasants’s book is to argue that would-be ‘post-positivist’ leading lights of contemporary social theory -- especially, Bhaskar, Giddens, and Habermas -- are actually still falling into the same traps of scientism and misbegotten epistemology as their positivist predecessors.[14] Moreover, Pleasants lays out in effective detail what I have had space here only to sketch the barest outlines of: namely, Wittgenstein’s antipathy to ‘theory’ in inappropriate places, and how this can be spelt out in relation to ‘social science’.[15] (Unfortunately, as I shall discuss shortly, even Pleasants fails to be sufficiently sympathetic to Winch’s own perspective on these matters -- Pleasants characterizes Winch [16] as a (more or less unwitting) fomentor of and participant in ‘critical social theory’.)

 

            Winch, I am urging, can and should be read as rejecting a place for ‘theory’ in accounts of social reality, if by ‘theory’ we mean anything much like the various things that the likes of Durkheim, Friedman, Bhaskar, or Bourdieu appear to mean by it.

            “But”, an interlocutor may interrupt, “how can this be? For, whether or not you are right about Wittgenstein, clearly Winch at least does have a theory, one centred around the notion of a rule.”

            Does Winch have a rule-based social theory? Many have thought so, based on their reading(s) of ISS. A major contemporary ‘Wittgensteinian’ author who has critiqued Winch repeatedly on these grounds is Ted Schatzki. A striking but not unusual fact about Schatzki’s interpretation of Winch is that it pays no attention whatsoever to the 1990 Preface.

 

 

           

 

            In fact, it is I think Winch who is the authentic Wittgensteinian here, not Schatzki. Because Winch, unlike Schatzki, is undogmatic. Schatzki insists that the term “rule” must be eschewed. But, as I acknowledged above, in connection with the term ‘theory’, no term is though and through flawed or misleading. To think otheriwse is to fall back into the grip of an Augustinian misapprehension of the functioning of language. It is words in use which mean something or other, not single words in isolation.[17] So, the way in which Winch uses the term ‘rule’ may be at times ill-advised or risky -- as he himself admitted in 1990 -- but it is a similar mistake to that of verificationism/positivism to claim that we can rule out in advance [18] the possibility of Winchian rule-talk being helpful in our philosophical inquiries. But Winch never insisted on the term, nor for that matter against other terms. The maxim which he seems to be following is more like “I’ll settle for whatever way works to convey a certain contrast (e.g. between the social and the natural) which is therapeutically useful when people are prone to scientism and ‘ontological monism’”, than like “Let’s look for the one term -- it could for instance turn out to be ‘rule’, or ‘norm’, or ‘tradition’ -- which is theoretically correct and may solve all our problems.” The latter alternative, the search for the magic (quasi-scientific) word, is roughly Schatzki’s -- and this is perhaps not surprising, when placed in the broader context of the fact that Schatzki has his own (‘practice-theoretic’) account of social reality. He wants to follow Wittgenstein -- but ends up doing so, it seems, much less than Winch.

            I have picked on Schatzki because he evidently wants to be a Wittgensteinian, and because there are moments in his work when he is tantalisingly close to Wittgenstein’s vision.[19] Nor is he alone among the recent writers on Winch in HHS; Pleasants takes Winch to be a ‘Kantian’

87-8 pl.

           

            I stress that Schatzki and Pleasants are, as it were, notionally right: if Winch did hold the kind of thesis about the absolute centrality to social life attributed to him by them, then he would indeed be guilty of a ‘metaphysical error’. But I have argued that, especially when we understand Winch as he asks us to understand him, we find him making no such error, or at worst using formulations at times that are uncomfortably similar to what someone would say who was making such an error.

 

            Illustrative of the difference in temperament between Winch and some of his critics is his distinctive reaction to the challenge presented by Kripke’s ‘rule-scepticism’. Many ‘Wittgensteinians’ have sought to refute Kripke, to answer him in one way or another. Most notable here perhaps are Baker and Hacker, in their polemical Scepticism, Rules and Language.Baker and Hacker rely on the concept of ‘internal relations’ to bind together rule and applcation. They do come awfully close to having a rule-centred (though individualist) ‘social’ philosophic theory.[20] A minority of ‘Wittgensteinians’ have instead embraced Kripke’s rule-scepticism as helping us to found a true social theory. Most notable here is David Bloor, in his Wittgenstein: A social theory of knowledge.[21] But some Wittgensteinians have refused altogether to take part in the debate on these terms. They have not tried to refute Kripke, but rather, to understand what is important and tenable in the human and linguistic roots of the challenge he tries to issue, and to deflate that purported challenge by means of issuing an invitation to the philosopher caught up in a Kripkean problematic to return to the everyday employments of the terms (e.g. ‘rule’, ‘interpretation’) which are at the heart of the matter. It is striking that Winch (1987) proceeds more or less explicitly in this manner, as more recently have done Cavell (1990) and Diamond (1989).[22]

            Schatzki and Pleasants do not go as far as Bloor, they appear to disagree only at the margin with his Kripkean belief in ‘undermining’ or criticising the concept of ‘rule’. For the likes of Bloor, ‘rules’ are a flawed element of a would-be social theory. For the likes of Baker and Hacker, ‘rules’ offer the tools to successfully rebut Kripkean scepticism. It is only Winch & co. who bypass this debate, out of the conviction that ‘rule’ is at base just another word of the English language, no more exceptional than ‘game’ or ‘chair’ or ‘microscope’.[23]

            Winch’s discussion of ‘rules’ and ‘internal relations’ in ISS etc. is then best read much differently from Baker and Hacker’s in their critique of Kripke.

 

            Winch is building on the Tractatus understanding of ‘internal relation’, which arguably persists into Wittgenstein’s later work [24]  -- as something strictly unsayable, a notion of transitional value at best. To further back up my thought about the non-assertoric, non-constative, therapeutic nature of Winch’s thought hereabouts, note the use of the notion of ‘internal relation’ on pp.xiv-xv of ISS:

 

. Contra Baker and Hacker, the term “internal relation” cannot be used faithfully to Wittgenstein in a way which provides a generalistic account of ‘metaphysical glue’ between rule and application -- this idea does deserve the kind of criticism which Schatzki (inappropriately) levels against Winch on rules.[25]

            ‘Internal relations’, for Winch as for Wittgenstein, are not genuinely relations. Only ‘external’ relations are actually relations, between separate things. And there have to be separate things, if there are to be relations (between things).

            It follows that when Winch speaks above of different ‘parts’ of social life, and similarly of social relations, as being ‘internal relations’, what he is really saying is usefully put as follows: that they are not relations at all. That characterizing them as relations can, riskily, lead to society being thought of in nonsensical atomistic ways. When we read Winch with a sensitivity to the non-assertoric, post-metaphysical nature of his philosophy, and when we attend to his attendance to the continuities in Wittgenstein’s philosophy (rather than, as is usual, reading in him at best only an alleged version of Wittgenstein’s (alleged) ‘later philosophy’), then profitable ways of understanding a multitude of his remarks in ISS open up for us. And unprofitable ways, contrariwise, are shut down. For example, when we pick up the notion of ‘internal relation’ for a while we see that, though it cannot be ultimately satisfactory, and though it can risk leading us to say things which sound awfully like (nonsensical) metaphysical ‘theses’ about the social world, it at least usefully closes down the unprofitable avenue of thinking of different practices as being (metaphysically) hermetically sealed off from one another; and furthermore suggests instead an alternative ‘picture’ which may help to point up the absurdity (not falsity) of the atomism and ontological individualism which have dominated much social theory.

            In sum, careful attention to Winch’s text and to its Wittgensteinian backdrop starts to show quite clearly how he resists being boxed into any ‘position’ in the conventional spectrum of social theories/philosophies -- whether ‘individualistic’ (e.g. Baker and Hacker) or ‘wholistic’ (e.g. Bloor).

 

 

 

            “You might have a point”, my interlocutor may say, “in arguing that Winch does not hold the “rules thesis” attributed to him by Pettit,[26] or the (very similar) rule-ubiquity theses attributed to him by Pleasants and Schatzki. Perhaps these ‘theses’ are at most truisms for Winch, not controversial and fruitful social-theoretic claims. But in that case, how do you account for Winch’s remarks about metaphysics, and social philosophy?”

[Reply]

 

Perhaps now the interlocutor interrupts impatiently, “But what do ‘different’ and ‘same’ mean, for Winch? How, for example, is the notion of ‘same community’ or ‘different community’ operationalised in the first place?”

            To answer the second question first: it is not. To answer the first question: These terms mean nothing at all for Winch -- as parts of a theory.Of course, they can mean everything in the rich and sometimes conflicting lives of real people from (or not from) real particular communities (see the closing paragraphs of the Preface to ISS [ and Lassman?]). Why think that we need philosophers / social theorists to individuate communities or otherwise, when people are so busy already doing it for themselves? What could such a theoretical individuation be, other than an attempted imposition of a simplified dummy reality on our complexand conflicted world?

            “But this is ridiculous! Every time you are pressed to clarify ehat you mean by a term, or what one of Winch’s notions amounts to, you say “It doesn’t mean anything.”!

            Right! It doesn’t mean anything -- as part of a theory. Roughly: only insofar as a theory were being put forward would one’s claims be truth-evaluable, would what one says turn out to be true or false. But there is no good reason to think that this is what Winch is doing.

            ‘But isn’t it true that the Azande are (were) a relatively homogenous culture relative to our’s, and that their culture is (was) relatively isolated from others, from other communities?”

            Now we have rapidly moved from an exclusively philosophic terrain to a question which is at least partly a simple matter of fact, or at least of empirical social description. The answer to your question is ‘Yes’, probably -- at least, for all I know, it is. The real question is: What philosophic or social-theoretic weight can be put on this ‘Yes’? What interesting consequences follow from this historical / common-sensical point for philosophy of mind or language, or for the validity or otherwise of (e.g.) Giddens’s picture of the human agent? Surely, none at all. The problem of other communities is simply a contemporary version of the old problem of other minds.[27] It can be just as phenomenologically real -- but to someone in its grip, either notionally or really,[28] theory is an irrelevance. Therapy is called for, instead.

           

Winch, like certain other recent philosophers (I have in mind particularly Thomas Kuhn), has been almost endlessly and more or less tragically misunderstood. Admittedly, the way he wrote, and some of his polemical and thought-provocative formulations, like Kuhn’s, gave away hostages to fortune. Thereafter the hostages were murdered over and over again, and therefore their ghosts still, regrettably, walk among us. If Winch’s ghost is to have peace, then the ghost of his ghost, the phantasm of those hostages, must be laid to rest. This will require philosophers and theorists of the social sciences to find a way no longer to hear Winch himself as a fantasist, with incoherent mumblings of a Relativistic or Idealistic nature forever behind his lips. Winch never meant to be a social theorist or a philosopher with a metaphysical message. I have tried to suggest here how he can be read otherwise than as that. But it requires an effort of will to follow my suggestions.

            Wittgenstein once suggested that philosophers confronted with our own -- their own -- ordinary lives and words are like primitive peoples confronted with the artifacts of modern civilizations. Philosophers (e.g. of the social sciences) typically lose their concepts,[29] lose their footing in their everyday practices, when they reflect on those practices. Ditto ‘social scientists’. And so both tend to substitute for those practices, in all their vast complexity and subtlety, crude two-dimensional substitutes.

            Winch once skected a way of avoiding doing this in connection with an influential example, that of (Evans-Pritchard’s) Azande. How ‘ironic’ that most of the way Winch has been treated in the ‘literature’ involves just the kind of primitive misunderstanding -- both of his topic and of his text -- that he himself warned against.[30] The misunderstandings of him which have predominated among philosophers and others can be alleviated -- but not by any theory, and not by any reader unwilling to do the work for themselves.

 

 

Bibliography

 

Gordon Baker and Peter Hacker, Scepticism, Rules and Language (Oxford: Blackwell, 1984).

 

Roy Bhaskar, The possibility of naturalism (Brighton: Harvester, 1979).

 

David Bloor, Wittgenstein: A social theory of knowledge (London: Macmillan, 1983).

                  , “The question of linguistic idealism revisited”, in Sluga and Stern (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein (Cambridge: C.U.P., 1996).

 

Stanley Cavell, “The argument of the ordinary: Scenes of Instruction in Wittgenstein and in Kripke”, in his Conditions Handsome and Unhandsome (Chicago: U.Chicago Pr., 1990).

Alice Crary & Rupert Read (eds.), The New Wittgenstein (London: Routledge, 2000).

Alice Crary, “Wittgenstein and political philosophy

Cora Diamond, “Losing your concepts”, Ethics 98 (January 1988), pp.255-277.

                    “ , “Rules: Looking in the right place”, in Phillips and Winch (eds.), Wittgenstein: Attention to particulars (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1989).

 

James Guetti and Rupert Read, “Acting from Rules”, International Studies in Philosophy XXVIII: 2 (1996).

 

Richard Hamilton, “Understanding Winch, Understanding Ourselves” (unpublished).

      

Colin Lyas, Peter Winch (Teddington, Mx: Acumen, 1999).

 

Nigel Pleasants, Wittgenstein and the idea of a critical social theory (London: Routledge, 1999).

                      , “Winch and Wittgenstein on understanding ourselves critically: descriptive, not metaphysical” (forthcoming).

 

Rupert Read, "The Unstatability of Kripkian Scepticisms", in Philosophical                  Papers  XXIV: 1 (1995).

                   , "The career of 'internal relations' in Wittgenstein's thought", in             Wittgenstein Studies 2 (1997).

                  , “What “There can be no such thing as meaning anything by any word” could possibly mean”, in Crary and Read (2000).

                   , “Is there a legitimate way to raise doubts about the immediate future 'from the perspective of' a doubted immediate past? : The case of Kripke”, in Wittgenstein Studies.(in press).

 

Lynette Reid, “Wittgenstein’s Ladder: The Tractatus and Nonsense”, Phil. Investigations 21 (1988), pp.97-151.

 

Louis Sass, The Paradoxes of Delusion (Ithaca: Cornell, 1994).

 

Ted Schatzki, “Wittgenstein and the social context of an individual life”, History of the Human Sciences 13:1 (2000), pp.93-107.

                   , “The Prescription is Description”, in Mitchell and Rosen (eds.), The need for interpretation (London: Athlone, 1983).

                   , “Elements of a Wittgensteinian Philosophy of the Social Sciences”, Synthese 87 (1991), pp.311-329.

 

Peter Winch, “The Unity of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy”, in his edited collection, Studies in the Philosophy of Wittgenstein (London: Routledge, 1969).

 

Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture and Value (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980).

                              “ , Philosophical Investigations (London: Macmillan, 1958).

 



[1] As will become evident, I believe that almost all of the 1990 Preface can be read as explicating the 1958 text, rather than revising it. Winch frequently refers to the unfortunate way he put things in the first edition of ISS; he rarely suggests that it needs to be substantively revised. On the single occasion where he does, I think, suggest substantive revision (see below), I personally would be inclined to accept the revision (while conceding, of course, that it is a revision).

[2] The publication date of “Understanding a Primitive Society.” Most critics do give this paper some attention -- even though few of them seem to understand it, and few seem to use Winch’s later work to help themselves do so.

[3] The two exceptions to the general rule, in my opinion, are Lynch and (perhaps) Lassman. !!??????

[4] For detail, see for instance Bhaskar’s (1979).

[5] For further explication and exemplification of the ‘logical method’ I am employing here, see p.102f. f Stone’s (2000).

[6] Unfortunately, Rorty sometimes fails into a trap somewhat analogous to that which he has delineated in the work of Jameson and others. I.e. He writes as if it must be obvious to anyone with a modicum of intelligence that such and such a position (e.g. advocacy of ‘liberal democracy’) is now uncontestable, or that such and such a theory (e.g. Darwinism) has inevitable philosophical or ethical consequences.

[7] The ‘Winchians’ tend to be sceptical of the ‘Diamondians’ claim that Wittgenstein’s early work can be resolutely interpreted in this fashion (see for instance Reid’s 1998). There is more agreement on the later work, and thus on Wittgenstien’s enduring legacy.

[8] See for instance the close of Crary’s 2000. Cf. also Nigel Pleasants’s recent work, and Gavin Kitching’s      .

[9] See especially Cavell’s 1990 and Stone’s 2000.

[10] For examples, see Witherspoon’s (2000) critique of tendencies in the thought of renowned Wittgenstein scholars Marie McGinn and Peter Hacker.

[11] PI para. 109. Wittgenstein goes on: “And this description gets its light, that is to say its purpose, from the philosophical problems. These are, of course, not empirical problems; they are solved, rather, by looking into the workings of our language, and that in such a way as to make us recognize those workings: in despite of an urge to misunderstand them. the problems are solved, not by giving new informattion, but by arranging what we have always known. Philosophy is a battle against the bewitchment of our intelligence by means of language.” For more on Wittgenstein’s understanding of theory, and his antipathy to theory in philosophy, see especially his (1980), p.28, 32, & 44. For more on the sense in which Winch does (and does not) oppose the giving of explanatory theories, see p.82 of Pleasants’s (2000).

[12] See the opening chapters of Colin Lyas’s Peter Winch (           ).

[13] See ISS p      .

[14] Moreover, that their politicised ‘knowingness’ is more or less necessarily coupled with actual political impotence, and is thus a counter-productive use of time and energy, for anyone serious about changing their society. Pleasants believes that on this score, Winch -- often derided as a ‘conservative’ Swansea Wittgensteinian -- has a more genuine ‘critical’ edge to his philosophisizing than these self-consciously leftist contemporary academics. See for instance his recent paper in HHS, and his (forthcoming).

[15] See the first two chapters of his (1999). The reader is strongly advised to consult these, if dissatisfied with my own far-too-summary critique of theory in philosophy and related domains.

[16] See Chapter 3 of his (1999).

[17] A full discussion of this point would require a detailed rendition of the New Wittgensteinian take on the importance of Frege’s “Context Principle” in Wittgenstein’s thought. A brief primer on this can be found in my (2000).

[18] As for instance Carnap famously rules out that Heidegger’s “The nothing itself nothings” can be possibly mean anything. For disscussion, see p.318f. of Witherspoon’s (2000).

[19] Cf. especially p.137 of his (1983), p.104 of his HHS paper, and perhaps p.319 of his (1991).

[20] My own arguments detailing why any follower of Diamond will question and reject their position are to be found in my (1996; jointly written with James Guetti) and my (1997).

[21] 1983. At the recent BSA/HHS ‘Peter Winch’ Conference in Bristol, Bloor evinced surprise that Winch too had not embraced Kripke. This surprise stems, I believe, from Bloor’s total lack of comprehension of the idea of a non-theoreticist philosophy, of a philosophy wherein words are truly brought back from metaphysical holiday to their everyday employments. See also p.378 of Bloor’s (1996).

[22] Diamond’s paper is in a collection co-edited by Winch. Other ‘New Wittgensteinian’ critiques of Kripke include Stone (2000), and Read (1995 and in press).

[23] Cf. PI para.s 116-121.

[24] See again my 1996 (joint with Guetti) and 1997.  Winch of course emphasized the continuities in Wittgenstein’s philosophy much more than is usually appreciated -- he ‘pioneered’ the ‘New Wittgenstein’ interpretation of the continuity of the Tractatus with the Investigations, in his (1969).

[25] See again my “Acting from rules” for detail as to where Baker and Hacker go wrong.

[26] See p.64f. of his (2000).

[27] This point is expanded on beautifully by Richard Hamilton in his (unpublished).

[28] I have in mind Louis Sass’s portrait of some sufferers from schizophrenia as would-be real-life solipsists -- see his 1994.

[29] In Cavell’s sense -- for explication, see Cora Diamond’s 1988.

[30] For some chapter and verse in the case of the ‘critical social theorists’, see p.83 of Pleasants’s (2000).